Sections :
When people talk of knowledge, they often consider only 'factual'
knowledge, like the knowledge we have discussed so far, of scientific or
mathematical truths. However, I would also want to say that I know that
murdering someone is wrong: I do not just feel or strongly believe this, I know
it.
I am aware, of course, that some of the moral
truths I know, or claim to know, are not accepted by everyone else. An example
is that I am against the death penalty on moral grounds; (one can be against it
on practical grounds too, as being ineffective.) But some other people, who
hold moral views different from mine and consider the death penalty a just
punishment, also claim to have knowledge of moral truths.
What we shall therefore have to discuss in this
section is how we justify claims to know moral truths. Whereas in subjects like
the natural sciences and mathematics, and even in history, it is generally
agreed how we should justify claims to knowledge, (even if there are of course
times when it is not known whether a particular proposition is true or not,)
there seems to be no such consensus on when to accept a proposition as
expressing a moral truth. So we shall have to consider the nature of moral
propositions, and the grounds on which we can claim to know them to be true.
Note that whereas ethics is the branch of philosophy concerned with moral values, the ethics or morals of an individual or a group are the values according to which they act.
Exercise 1.1
We have distinguished before between three types of propositions: empirical, normative and metaphysical. Which of the following statements express propositions of the three types? Discuss how you would argue for or against each of them.
a.2 + 2 = 5
b.You are a figment of my imagination.
c.That painting is beautiful.
d.Giving is better than taking.
e.Truth is Beauty.
f.The sun is bigger than the moon.
One of the characteristics of normative propositions is that they are categorical, i.e. unconditional, unqualified, absolute. Thus, one of the following statements does not quite make sense. Which one?
a.70% of offenders who have not received corporal punishment re-offend, but only 40% of those who have.
b.Corporal punishment is 30% right.
c.30% of the population believe that corporal punishment is right.
d.Corporal punishment is right in 30% of the cases.
Exercise 1.2
We have to distinguish two meanings of the word ''moral''. Try to describe the difference between the statements in the following pairs.
a.They had a moral debate. -- They always acted very morally.
b.Prostitution is immoral. -- The problem of prostitution is amoral.
Note that some words can be used either morally or amorally (i.e. non-morally.) Try to describe the differences between the statements in the following pairs.
a.That was a good meeting. -- That was a good deed.
b.He had a good life. -- He led a good life.
c.What they said was right. -- They did the right thing.
Moral actions typically involve a person, the 'agent', doing something and a person or some thing which something is done to, the 'recipient' of the action, (who may be the same as the agent: for instance when I do something, like reading good books, to improve myself.)
Exercise 1.3
In which way do you think the following figure in our moral discourse: as agents, as recipients of actions, both, or neither?
a.inanimate objects,
b.our natural environment,
c.animals,
d.small children,
e.responsible adults.
Think of examples of situations where we would not hold someone morally responsible for something they have done.
One of the basic choices we make -- and it is itself a moral choice -- is to what actions we apply moral judgments, and we can evade moral criticism by restricting the range of what we consider moral.
Conservatives have often of course proved obsessive on the topic of sexuality, viewing morality as about adultery rather than armaments, sexual deviancy rather than starvation.
Democracy is not the absence of ranking: on the contrary, it involves privileging the interests of the people as a whole over the interests of anti-social power-groups. Everyone subscribes to some hierarchy of values, a commitment which is arguably constitutive of the self. As Charles Taylor puts it [in Sources of the Self, 1989]: ''To know who you are is to be oriented in moral space, a space in which questions arise about what is good or bad, what is worth doing and what not, what has meaning and importance for you and what is trivial and secondary.'' Valuing belongs with social identity, and social life would grind to a halt without it.
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, 1996.
I am a Jew. Hath not a Jew eyes? Hath not a Jew hands, organs, dimensions, senses, affections, passions ...? If you prick us, do we not bleed? If you tickle us, do we not laugh? If you poison us, do we not die? And if you wrong us, shall we not revenge?)
Exercise 1.4
Give other examples of the different ways sketched
above, to avoid moral judgment, or evade moral criticism.
Can you think of other such ways of considering
actions as amoral, or outside morality?
Normative propositions can be of different forms:
Exercise 2.1
For each of the following value judgments, state whether it is moral or non-moral, whether of obligation or of value, and whether it is general or particular.
a.You deserve to be punished.
b.Democracy is the best form of government.
c.The man who can forgive such carelessness is a saint.
d.I ought not escape from prison now.
e.You just have to go to that concert.
f.That is a good car.
g.All men have a right to freedom.
h.In building a bookcase one should use nails, not just glue.
It is manifest that morality has social aspects: not only do our moral values depend in part on how we have been brought up, but morality is closely related to systems of social regulation, like the law and good manners.
Exercise 2.2
The sociologist David Riesman, in The Lonely Crowd, 1950, portrayed four moral or social types; try to briefly characterize these types, and give examples.
a.the tradition-directed individual (and/or society,)
b.the inner-directed individual (and/or society,)
c.the other-directed individual (and/or society,)
d.the autonomous individual (and/or society.)
Exercise 2.3
Discuss the following questions.
a.In which respects is morality like the law and unlike conventions?
b.In which respects is morality like conventions and unlike the law?
c.Can a person stranded alone on a desert island act immorally?
d.In which way, if any, do animals figure in our morality?
Some people hold the view that morality is no more than a system of social
regulation, or perhaps a kind of personal feeling; or that it is only a matter of
opinion anyhow -- and there may be no way of proving such people 'wrong,'
(although one may choose not to associate with them ...) These kinds of views
are called 'reductionist': they reduce moral value to other, simpler things
like statistics, or psychology.
However, even if we often don't agree in our moral
judgments, a wide range of values seem to be universal -- in the sense that we
might even question someone's humanity if they did not hold them.
What is under ... fire, however, is perhaps less the notion of some practical ranking of priorities than the assumption that such priorities are eternal and immutable. ... But there seems nothing terribly objectionable about absolute hierarchies ... . It is hard to imagine a situation in which tickling the starving would be preferable to feeding them, or torturing people less reprehensible than teasing them.
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, 1996.
Moreover, even if we often don't agree in our moral judgments, we do seem to think of moral values as objective -- in the sense of being capable of justification by a certain kind of argument; and we do seem able to recognise moral arguments as such, even if personally we hold different values.
Exercise 2.4
How 'moral' do you think each of the following reasons is? What kind of reasons are those that are not moral?
''I believe I shouldn't take someone else's things, because ...
a.the Bible says I shouldn't.''
b.what would happen if everyone did that kind of thing?''
c.I might get caught and punished.''
d.I do not like my things being taken either.''
e.if I did, even if no one knew, I would be a thief.''
f.I would feel so bad afterwards.''
g.I was brought up that way.''
h.it would be a selfish thing to do.''
i.I don't need them.''
j.they need (or want) them as much as I do.''
You will probably agree that some of the above 'moral' arguments are valid while others are not. Try to give general characterisations of those that you consider are moral arguments.
Knowing a mathematical truth requires that one be able to give an
appropriate kind of justification: one must be able to prove it, say, or have
learnt it from someone of whom one can reasonably suppose that he is able to
prove it. Similarly, knowing what time it is requires having looked at a
working clock recently, or having heard the time signal on the radio, or having
asked someone with a watch; and so on. And knowing moral truths is no different,
which is the reason that we consider moral judgments in Theory of Knowledge.
Moral judgment, no less than scientific or
historical knowledge, depends on a particular kind of justification. I can
therefore recognise the opinion of another person as the result of a moral
judgment they have made -- rather than as no more than a prejudice, or a mere
expression of their feelings -- even if I do not agree with them. This is one
way in which morality is objective, despite the obvious fact that we don't all
agree in our moral judgements.
Whatever morality we hold, the requirements we make of moral arguments would presumably include the following:
It was not at all true in practice that everyone -- women, for example, or non-Europeans, or the lower peasantry -- was accorded equal respect. But everyone's freedom mattered in theory, and 'in theory' is a sizeable improvement on its not mattering even as that. It is an improvement not least because middle-class society could now be challenged by those it suppressed according to its own logic, caught out in a performative contradiction between what it said and what it did.
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, 1996.
Exercise 2.5
What, if anything, is wrong with the following denials? What general requirements do they fail to satisfy?
a.''I couldn't help it, I was drunk.''
b.''How could I have known he'd use the gun I sold him to shoot someone?''
c.''I always copy software: firms like Microsoft are so rich anyhow.''
d.''I didn't steal it. I just borrowed it and forgot to give it back.''
e.''Of course I am having fun right now; but when I marry, I am going to make sure my wife is a virgin.''
f.''I didn't have any choice: they threatened to kill me and my family.''
g.''I didn't kill anyone. I was just driving quickly to an important meeting when that silly person walked onto the road.''
h.''God told me to do it.''
In considering moral judgment it is not enough, though, to investigate what kinds of arguments we can use. As with other kinds of knowledge, the justification of a claim to know some moral truth ultimately requires some basis for the argument. In the case of science, for instance, we cannot avoid ultimately going back to perception. In the remainder of this chapter we shall consider different ways in which a morality can be grounded.
(Note that the various '-isms' which will be introduced in the remainder of this chapter are not intended as anything other than convenient labels: there is no agreed way of naming different moral positions.)
A necessary requirement for morality to be possible at all would appear to be that we have free will, or be capable of it: i.e. we must be free to do as we choose (-- which is, however, different from behaving randomly!) How else can we be responsible for our actions, and they subject to moral judgment?
Exercise 3.1
Discuss what it means for a decision -- to study a certain subject at university, for instance -- to have been taken freely. What kinds of things make us unfree?
DETERMINISM is the view that every event, including human volitions and choices, is caused by other events and happens as an effect or a result of these other events, so that the freedom of choice we appear to have is an illusion.
Exercise 3.2
On what grounds might someone hold a determinist
position? Try to distinguish different kinds of determinism.
Try to think of some argument against each kind of determinism.
FATALISM is the stronger view -- or perhaps a basic emotional attitude -- that every event occurs according to a fixed and inevitable destiny, over and above mere causality, and that what we do is wholly controlled by something independent of our choices and desires. This is the position expressed in the following limerick:
There was a young man who said: ''Damn!
It grieves me to think that I am
Predestined to move
In a circumscribed groove:
In fact, not a bus, but a tram.''
Exercise 3.3
Fatalism denies the efficacy of the human will and
so is clearly incompatible with moral responsibility, but is that true of
determinism as well?
Can you see how we might be morally responsible, even if the determinist was
right?
Like many philosophical problems, the question of free will and
determinism, and whether we can be morally responsible, although it has been
discussed and argued about for many centuries, has not been resolved.
But here is an attempt -- based on ideas of the
American philosopher Donald Davidson -- that may go some way towards an answer:
While in the world there are only things and events, we can think of events
only in terms of their descriptions, such as ''a ball hitting the ground.''
But certain events are capable of having essentially
different descriptions: thus, the same event can be described as my arm moving
upwards, or as my moving my arm up. The first is a physical description, the
second a psychological one in terms of my intention or will.
Similarly, another event can be described as the pulling
of a trigger, as the deliberate killing of someone I dislike, or as
cold-blooded murder. The first is a physical, the second a psychological, and
the third a moral description.
Now, if the different descriptions of an event were such
that they could not be translated into each other in an automatic way, then it
would be possible for events to be related deterministically, as cause and
effect, under the physical description, but not under their moral description.
What kind of description we use for an event is a (partly
moral) choice we make: it would be odd to talk of the 'love' of the electron
for the positive plate, but immoral to talk of the holocaust without taking a
moral stand. So if we choose to talk of human actions in moral terms, then we
can assume free will and avoid the conflict with determinism.
Exercise 3.4
To give substance to the above very brief summary of a difficult philosophical argument, try to answer the following questions:
a.What might be the cause of my arm moving upwards, and what the reason for my moving my arm up?
b.Which of the following descriptions would you consider as physical, which as psychological, and which as moral?
They share many interests and enjoy one another's company.
They are close friends.
They spend a lot of time together.
c.Give physical, psychological and moral descriptions of some other events.
d.Have you come across words or sentences in your language that it has not been possible to translate completely into another language, so that you could not express the same thing in the other language?
There are different outlooks on which a person's morality may be based, and
on the basis of which they put forward moral arguments. It is helpful to divide
these into three groups.
(The philosophers whose names are here associated
with particular views are representative only; and in most cases a range of
different versions and developments of the basic position can be found. It is
also worth bearing in mind that these are philosophical
positions, and that in many cases the advocates of a view may not have lived by
it themselves ... )
On some accounts of morality there are no specifically moral values at all, and what we need to do is just give a psychological explanation of the origin of morality, or to 'explain morality away.'
One
version of this is ETHICAL EGOISM (from Lat. ego, I) put forward by Thomas Hobbes, 1588 -1679, a
political philosopher (Leviathan, 1651.)
Rather than trying to justify moral values or
judgments, ethical egoism merely accounts for them in terms of man's character:
starting from the principle that everyone always acts out of self-interest, it
maintains that an action is called right just because it is in the interest of
the agent.
It is because homo homini lupus [''man is as a wolf to man''], so that in
the state of nature there is bellum omnium contra omnes [''war of all against all''] and the life
of man is ''solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short,'' that people must
submit to the absolute supremacy of the state, the great Leviathan, which is
pictured as like a human being, whose health is peace, and whose soul is the
sovereign: he establishes morality, he creates the law.
(The opposite of egoism is ALTRUISM (from Lat. alter, the other,) according to which the good
of others is the ultimate end for any moral action.)
On some other accounts there are moral values according to which we should act, but these are derived from the non-moral consequences our actions have, such as individual pleasure, or happiness. Therefore such theories are called consequentialist or teleological (from Gk. telos, end, purpose.) According to consequentialist views, the morality of an action is determined solely by its consequences.
A
typical example is UTILITARIANISM (from Lat. utilitas, usefulness, advantage,) which was founded
by Jeremy Bentham, 1748 -1832, and then developed by John Stuart Mill, 1806
-1873.
According to Bentham, our actions should maximize
the balance of pleasure over pain, for which he devised scales to be able to
compare them; and since a greater interest should not be given up for a smaller
one, the morally right action is that which produces the greatest happiness of
the greatest number.
Whereas Bentham had only recognised the intensity
of pleasures and pains, so that ''quality of pleasure being equal, [the game
of] push-pin is as good as poetry,'' Mill distinguished pleasures and pains of
different qualities and maintained that ''it is better to be a human being
dissatisfied than a pig satisfied.''
And whereas according to Bentham the utilitarian
principle was to be applied to each action separately, Mill argued that it
should be used to establish moral rules which would generally produce the
greatest happiness for the greatest number.
On the third kind of outlook, moral value resides in some aspect of the action itself, and depends either not at all or only partly on its consequences: after all, these consequences can often not be foreseen. Such theories are called non-consequentialist or deontological (from Gk. deon, duty.) Deontological theories claim, variously, that the morality of an action depends on its intrinsic nature, or on its motives, or on its being in accordance with some rule or principle.
An
example of such a position is the FORMALISM of Immanuel Kant, 1724 -1804: if
morality is to be objective and universal, it can only be founded on pure
reason, and reason has two kinds of demands: whereas
a
'hypothetical imperative' tells me how to act to reach a particular end, the
'categorical imperative' dictates a course of action because it is right.
This categorical imperative, which is the only
moral law, characterizes the form of moral actions and is in fact a
restatement, in logical form, of 'the golden rule' -- to do unto others as you
would have others do unto you: ''Act only on a maxim which you can will,
through your action, [without logical contradiction] to become
a universal law'' (Principles of the Metaphysics of Ethics, 1785.)
This being the only moral law, moral worth can be accorded to an action,
however beneficial etc. it may be, only in so far as it is done out of a duty
to follow its requirement.
Kant further derives a principle that has been
adopted by various modern philosophers, that one must treat others as ''in
every case an end, never as a means only.''
Exercise 4.1
Try to construct moral arguments for protecting the environment according to each of the three positions outlined above.
Exercise 4.2
Using examples to illustrate your points, discuss what it is that we make moral judgments of: is it the agent, his action, his motives, or something else?
Exercise 4.3
Choose one of the moral positions from the overview below, and prepare a brief résumé (summary) of it, for presentation to the class in a lesson.
Whatsoever is the object of any man's appetite or desire, that is it which he for his part calleth good; and the object of his hate and aversion evil. ... these words are ever used with relation to the person that useth them; there being nothing simply and absolutely so; nor any common rule of good and evil to be taken from the nature of the objects themselves.
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, 1651.
A
counter-argument by Bishop Joseph Butler (1692 -1752) :
Suppose B wants A to enjoy the sight of the ocean:
the egoist is committing a logical error, in confusing the object of B's desire
-- A's enjoying the ocean -- with the satisfaction that results for B when the
object is attained. That this is an error can be seen by considering the case
of B failing to get A to the ocean, or A not enjoying it: would in that case
his lack of satisfaction been B's goal?
The notion of morals implies some sentiment common to all mankind, which
recommends the same object to general approbation. ... when a man denominates
another his enemy, his rival, his antagonist, his adversary, he is understood
to speak the language of self-love, and to express sentiments peculiar to
himself, and arising from his particular circumstance and situation. But when
he bestows on any man the epithets of vicious or odious or depraved, he then
speaks another language and expresses sentiments in which he expects all his
audience are to concur with him. He must here ... depart from his private and
particular situation, and must choose a point of view, common to himself with
others. ... [So mankind had to] invent a peculiar set of terms, in order to
express those universal sentiments of censure or approbation. ... Virtue and
vice become then known; morals are recognized; certain general ideas framed of
human conduct and behaviour. ...
I esteem the man whose self-love, by whatever means, is so
directed as to give him a concern for others, and render him serviceable to
society; as I hate and despise him who has no regard to anything beyond his own
gratifications and enjoyments div class=ref>David Hume, An Enquiry
Concerning the Principles of Morals, 1751.
There are various versions of Hume's position, differing in how many people are expected to share the moral sentiments:
Appealing and open-minded though this appears, cultural relativism, not only in ethics, is not borne out by our experience.
Cultural relativism ... imagines that different cultures are wholly self-validating and mutually incommensurable. Even if there were some sort of rationality in common between them, it would first have to be translated into both cultures' entirely different terms and so, presuming that they could identify it at all, would instantly cease to offer common ground. Hardly anyone actually responds like this when they run into someone from another culture; nobody actually behaves as though there was nothing in common between them, whatever the daunting difficulties of mutual dialogue. But the case has stubbornly survived its empirical implausibility
Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, 1996.
Counter-argument by G. E. Moore: that all such theories are guilty of the 'naturalist fallacy', of deriving normative conclusions from purely factual premises.
It may well be true that everything that is good is also something else (pleasant, for instance), just as it is true that everything that is yellow gives rise to light of a certain kind ... But all too many philosophers have believed that by describing this other they are defining the quality 'good'
G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica, 1903.
The only evidence we can produce that something is desirable is that people
actually desire it.
... if human nature is so constituted as to desire nothing
which is not either a part of happiness [-- which here means pleasure --] or a
means to happiness, we can have no other proof, and we require no other, that
these are the only things desirable. [He then argues that human nature is so
constituted and concludes that pleasure, and pleasure alone, is good as an end,
basically at least:]
... pleasure and freedom from pain are the only things
desirable as ends
Mill, Utilitarianism, 1863.
EGOISTIC
HEDONISM : Aristippos (435 - 355), the Cyrenaics
The supreme end of existence is the gratification of one's own immediate
personal desires.
RATIONAL
HEDONISM : Epicurus (341 - 270)
Although nowadays (according to the O.E.D.) an Epicurean is a
person ''devoted to refined sensuous enjoyment,'' Epicurus actually did not
recommend every momentary pleasure of the flesh; rather, to achieve the good
life, a life of moderate and enduring pleasure, a man must cultivate the
virtues, particularly prudence, and study philosophy.
(ACT-)UTILITARIANISM
: Jeremy Bentham (1748 -1832)
One ought to act in each situation so as achieve the greatest good for the
greatest number.
RULE
UTILITARIANISM : John Stuart Mill (1806 -1873)
One always ought to act according to the rules which will generally achieve the
greatest good for the greatest number.
Five counter-arguments:
The argument moves from saying that something is
the case to saying that something ought to be the case, i.e. it derives a value
judgment from a statement of fact.
The 'hedonist paradox': that if we consciously take
pleasure as our end, we somehow miss it, while if we pursue and attain other
things for their own sakes, we can gain pleasure.
Although, on the whole, actions which we consider
as morally good are ones that the utilitarian principle prescribes, are they
good because they give rise to the greatest happiness of the
greatest number?
If two acts produce the same balance of good over
evil, but such that they distribute that balance in different ways -- do they
have to be equally right?
''It is quite compatible with the principle of
utility that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than
others. ... It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig
satisfied'' (J. S. Mill.)
Human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue ... [which] is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean, i.e., the mean relative to us, this being determined by a rational principle ... by which the man of practical wisdom would determine it. Now it is a mean between two vices, that which depends on excess and that which depends on defect
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics.
Plato
(?427 - ?347) :
For Plato, morality is less a matter of rules or
principles than of dispositions, or traits of character: his is an ethics of
virtue.
To be virtuous is to be happy, and since all men
desire happiness, they always desire to act morally. Virtue being knowledge of
the Good, it can be taught, and when someone acts wrongly, he must be acting in
ignorance and just requires teaching (-- 'ethical optimism'.)
The four cardinal virtues consist in the right application
of our three faculties: the virtues particular to reason, to feelings and to
desires are wisdom, courage and temperance; but the highest virtue is justice,
both towards oneself, i.e. between one's various faculties, and towards others.
Max
Scheler (1874 -1928) :
From the phenomenological perspective, specific
moral values present themselves directly to consciousness, they are
self-evident and not in need of justification by any form of argument,
psychological or (contrary to Kant's view) logical.
Ethics can actually teach us what is morally good, just as geometry can teach us what is geometrically true [-- by deriving it from axioms that are intuitively obvious]
Nicolai Hartmann, Ethics, 1926.
G. E. Moore (1873 -1958) :
Or it may be the quality of goodness that is
self-evident, not apprehended by sense experience but intuitively, in such things
as friendship and aesthetic experience; morality is then the means to bring
about that goodness.
Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself. That is the first principle of existentialism. ... To choose between this or that is at the same time to affirm the value of that which is chosen; for we are unable ever to choose the worse. ... When a man commits himself to anything, fully realizing that he is not only choosing what he will be, but is thereby at the same time a legislator deciding for the whole of mankind -- in such a moment a man cannot escape from the sense of complete and profound responsibility. ... What is at the very heart and centre of existentialism, is the absolute character of the free commitment, by which every man realizes himself in realizing a type of humanity -- a commitment always understandable, to no matter whom in no matter what epoch -- and its bearing upon the relativity of the cultural pattern which may result from such absolute commitment. ... Man makes himself; he is not found ready-made; he makes himself by the choice of his morality, and he cannot but choose a morality, such is the pressure of circumstances upon him
Sartre, Existentialism and Humanism, 1946.
N's Life:
1844 |
is born, in Saxony; |
|
1864 - |
studies first in Bonn, then in Leipzig; |
|
1869 - |
professorship in philology
in Basel; |
|
1870 |
voluntary medical orderly in the German-French war; |
|
1873 - |
beginning illness: headaches, eye and stomach troubles; |
|
1879 - |
has to stop teaching owing
to bad health; |
|
1889 - |
mentally ill, looked after by his sister Elisabeth; |
|
1900 |
dies; (notebooks published posthumously as The Will to Power.) |
Family:
father:
a pious Protestant minister, died when N was 5 --
N brought up by women;
mother:
possessively attached to her son;
sister, Elisabeth:
sometimes a help to N, often his scourge;
married an anti-Semitic activist, Förster, who tried to found a Teutonic colony
in Paraguay;
took on role of sole interpreter of N's thought after his collapse, and death;
no wife, (though he considered a marriage, in 1877.)
Studies:
first theology, (though later he rejected Christianity --
perhaps most famous for his ''God is dead.'')
classical philology:
hence ancient Greek culture as the ideal and Greek
tragedy as the model art;
hence also: emphasis on careful interpretation;
Schopenhauer (1788 --1860):
man cannot recognize the true nature of things (cf.
Kant)
and is subject to his selfish will (cf. N's will to power, Freud's libido) --
even in his morality;
hence redemption can come only by willingly denying the will in moral action,
or by the contemplation of beauty.
Friends:
Jacob Burckhardt, 1818 -1897, professor of history in Basel,
author of Weltgeschichtliche Betrachtungen, (lectures in 1870,) etc.
Richard Wagner, 1813 -1883
1868: |
first meeting, |
1869: |
infatuated with Wagner --
and/or his wife Cosima? |
1873: |
tensions, |
1876: |
final break, |
Peter Gast, a young composer (-- N had tried composing, too)
from 1875: admirer, friend, supporter, editor;
N even tried to champion Gast's compositions;
the young Lou Andrea Salomé,
who later knew Freud, and 'collected' other famous people.
Character, Personality:
an outsider at school;
a quiet, polite, unassuming gentleman,
but with ''piercing eyes,'' who could become forceful in his speech;
his illness, and his ambivalence towards it:
pain etc. -- but sickness gives one time to think,
pain liberates;
hence sickness necessary to achieve ''the great health;''
mankind may be sick -- but hence interesting.
that N was anti-Semitic:
in fact he was outspokenly anti-anti-Semitic:
''since Wagner had been in Germany again, he had
descended step by step to everything I despise -- even to anti-Semitism ... It
was indeed high time for me to say good-bye'' (N contra Wagner,)
and
''What pleasure is a Jew amongst Germans!'' (Der Wille zur Macht,)
though he was concerned with Jews in his writings, (as was everyone;)
origin of the legend:
systematic mis-interpretation, by Elisabeth and
others, even forgeries have been discovered;
deliberate exploitation of his works by the Nazis, quoting out of context etc.
(cf. Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 1968, 1974, p. 290;): a travesty of Also
sprach Zarathustra, 1883 -1885, was distributed to German troops in
WWII.
that N was a proto-Nazi:
der Übermensch [''the over-man'']:
not a 'master race', the result of breeding or
evolution --
there is no plural (Übermenschen) or opposite (Untermensch) in N;
(he does talk of 'superior men' though: those who create themselves, and a
system of values;)
Herrenmoral [''master morality'']:
not the 'grand values' of some 'master race' --
the Nazi hordes are precisely who N would have considered 'slaves';
der Wille zur Macht [''the will to power'']:
not the simple desire to rule over others,
(although that is one of its possible expressions) --
rather it is the characteristic of all life forces.
that N need not be taken seriously:
because of his later insanity/ monomaniacal conceit,
e.g. wanted to found an anti-German league of
European nations,
in 1889 he signed himself ''the Crucified;''
but: we must avoid the ad hominem fallacy --
N himself: we must not confuse origin and value;
because his work is in bits and pieces, or contradictory, or just 'poetic':
thus, Karl Jaspers: ''the work lies as a pile of
debris,'' but ''the stones, already more or less hewn, point to a whole,'' and
we must ''not rest content at any place until we have also found its opposite
somewhere'' --
N himself: from the ''frog's perspective'' of believing in simple truth and
falsehood one cannot capture all that needs to be said;
N's elegance of style should be no argument against his philosophy, even if his
most poetic work Zarathustra is not a good place to start reading
him.
N the man of his time, the philologist:
veneration of genius,
esp. the ancient Greeks', Wagner's;
on history:
it distinguishes man from the animals,
but is dangerous:
brutal and senseless,
history is but the scorn of the victorious;
and romantic alienation from the present:
the agent was always without conscience,
only in the contemplation can there be conscience;
antidotes:
the unhistorical ability to forget,
the supra-historical insight that all is relative, all is becoming;
representative of the pessimism, the nihilism of his culture and his time.
N the free spirit, ''the first psychologist'':
icy truthfulness:
rejects romantic notions of genius now;
naturalist psychology:
aphorisms often amusing and full of insight:
''Tourists. -- They climb up the mountains
like animals, stupid and sweating; one has forgotten to tell them that there
are beautiful views on the way.''
''Lack of trust. -- Lack of trust between friends is a fault which
cannot be criticized without becoming incurable.''
a school of suspiciousness of surfaces:
''Why there are still beggars alive. -- If
alms were given out of kindness only, all beggars would by now have starved to
death.''
''Delicacy of shame. -- People are not ashamed to have dirty thoughts,
but are ashamed when they imagine that others might attribute such thoughts to
them.''
but we have to beware of misunderstandings:
''Beggars. -- Beggars should just be abolished: for one is annoyed when one gives something, and annoyed when one doesn't.''
against moral and religious prejudices,
against everything that reduces life and its
instincts,
esp. in the name of the supernatural:
''Luke 18.14 improved. -- He that humbleth himself wants to be exalted.'' (-- in the Bible: ''... shall be exalted.'')
N the immoralist:
on religion:
understanding why people believe in God,
e.g. because this life is so miserable,
and who benefits from religion:
the church, the priests, etc., suppressing human instincts
by means of guilt: ''God degenerated to a contradiction to life,''
e.g. one shows pity because it pleases God -- but in fact one just wants 'to go
to Heaven;'
one can ask: why believe in God?
so: ''God is dead.''
(not: ''There is no God.'' -- this would require metaphysical arguments, like
those that try to show that there is;)
on morality:
understanding why people have moral values,
e.g. so as to feel good, to have security,
and who benefits from moral systems:
i.e. the weak, the ''incurably mediocre,'' driven
by their ''herd instinct,'' and their resentments, wanting revenge against the
strong,
e.g. pity is good because it is unegoistic -- but in fact one is just thinking
of oneself;
one can rise above the Sklavenmoral [''slave morality''], according to which
usefulness, conformity = good,
strength, passion, independence = bad;
e.g. Christianity, nationalism;
Herrenmoral [''master morality''],
values Beyond Good and Evil, 1886:
not a prescriptive moral code,
but aristocratic individualism, (which has nothing to do with the aristocracy;)
represents a healthy egoism:
also due to selfishness,
but not just a living out of one's instincts: the strong need not assert
themselves aggressively or violently;
e.g. pity, now, is ''courtesy of the heart'' -- not due to striving for some
Heaven or avoiding a bad conscience;
the superior, noble man creates himself:
Werde der du bist! [''Become who you are!'']
e.g. Goethe, but also Cesare Borgia (a ruthless Renaissance ruler;)
N as an early existentialist:
each man is responsible for choosing his own
values,
so living by a system, or by one's instincts or desires, is being inauthentic,
(to use Sartre's term);
der Übermensch [''over-man''] is the expression of the individual's freedom,
is the self-overcoming of man;
N on N: ''I am no man, I am dynamite.''
The purpose of this section in the course can clearly not be to teach moral
values, nor to discuss particular moral issues, interesting though they might
be, other than as occasional examples, but must be to discuss the nature of
morality and moral argument.
I have found that there is quite commonly, (and not
only amongst Th.o.K. students,) a 'prejudice' against normative or
value-judgments, so that they are immediately pounced upon, and suspected of
being unfounded or manipulative. Whereas problems only arise, really, if the
different kinds of proposition are confused, if a value judgment is made as if
it was an empirical statement, say.
Exercise 1.2.:
''Amoral is frequently and incorrectly
used where immoral is meant. In careful usage, however, immoral is applied to that
which infringes moral rules and amoral is only used of that to which
considerations of morality are irrelevant or of persons who lack any moral
code'' (Collins English Dictionary, 1991.) -- Cf. also the
'morale' of a group and the 'moral' of a story.
The amoral judgments are extrinsic rather than
intrinsic, i.e. the event is judged according to some further purpose.
Exercise 1.3.:
Examples of when we would not hold someone morally responsible for something they have done:
ˇWhen a witch doctor has killed someone by a potion which he believed would 'dispatch' only evil spirits, though he may well be legally responsible;
ˇinsanity, which is accepted as a legal defence if the culprit would have done the same thing with a policeman standing next to him (M'Naghten rules, 1843;)
ˇperhaps temporary insanity, as in pathological jealousy -- although a 'crime of passion' may be due to weak self-control rather than to overwhelming passion.
But not:
ˇintoxication, unless the state has been reached without one's own actions;
ˇacting under duress, where one does have a choice how to act, even if the choice one makes is obvious and right (-- the bank manager who has handed over his employer's money because his family was being held hostage is lessening his standing as a full, responsible human being if he denies that he acted as a free agent who made the obvious choice.)
Exercise 1.4.:
Another way: one can consider actions that are done as part of a large group, or that are socially sanctioned, as outside morality: for instance, many people who were involved in lynching would not have been violent as individuals.
2. The Nature of Moral ArgumentExamples of different kinds of moral judgments:
obligation |
value |
|
general |
We ought to keep our promises. |
To keep one's promises is a virtue. |
particular |
He should have kept his promise. |
Not keeping his promise was selfish. |
Exercise 2.1.:
non-moral |
moral |
|||
obligation |
value |
obligation |
value |
|
general |
h. |
b. |
g. |
c. |
particular |
e. |
f. |
d. |
a. |
Exercise 2.2.:
a.Goals and rules are defined externally, by one's culture in 'primitive' societies or one's parents, and followed indiscriminately.
b.Adult authority, or social ideals and demands, have been internalized, but are supported by one's own reasoning.
c.Values formed chiefly by expectations of one's contemporaries, peers; 'escape from freedom': when anxiety leads to dependence, on the church, one's partner.
d.Requires constant questioning of one's morality, its origin and basis; rational inner-direction, an examined life.
Exercise 2.3.:
It is interesting that the roots of both the words, ''ethics'' (from Gk. ethós) and ''morality'' (from Lat. mores,) mean 'custom(s)' -- which is quite different from the meaning they have nowadays.
a.The law, like morality,
deals with more serious matters than conventions: theft and murder, rather than
what wine to have with what dish;
breaking with convention can be positive, but not breaking the law (except of
course in cases when ...) or going against morality;
in fact, the law is to some extent a formalisation and codification of moral
values.
b.Conventions, like morality, are not deliberately created, changed and maintained by some institution, like the law is, and they are less specific and have no formal sanctions attached.
d.Not usually as agents,
but as recipients of our action (cf. vegetarianism):
either out of consideration for or sympathy with them,
or out of consideration for how we act, i.e. what kinds of agents we are.
Exercise 2.4.:
Moral arguments may ...
ˇinvoke some general principles, ideals, virtues -- e.g. not to disregard the interest of others, not to kill.
ˇappeal to altruism -- e.g. ''Do unto others as you would have others do unto you.''
ˇre-describe the action or agent -- e.g. abortion can be called either murder, or just a surgical procedure.
ˇevaluate actions in terms of their motives and foreseeable consequences: this may depend on knowledge available, intellectual ability, etc. -- e.g. hurting someone when trying to help them.
(Could practise different arguments and non-argumments by considering jumping the queue at lunch instead of taking someone else's things.)
3. Free Will and DeterminismExercise 3.1.:
It must have been possible for us to act otherwise.
But can one ever know that? -- seeing that one only did what one did.
And am I not most determined in my action when I
was most free and decided most deliberately, with the best reasons?
Perhaps freedom can only be described negatively,
i.e. we can argue that we were not unfree in certain respects, e.g. free from our
parents' influence, or from a hidden desire for money or status, in choosing to
become a doctor.
Exercise 3.2.:
a.Religious: if ''the
eternal destiny of a person is predetermined by God's unchangeable decree,'' or
even if God only has foreknowledge of what they will do, how can the person --
even if it is Judas -- be held responsible?
''Predestination is determination plus the belief in a supernatural power that
has established a determining natural sequence of causes.''
b.Scientific: in Laplace's ''clockwork universe'', if only we knew all the 'initial conditions' well enough, we could predict all future events, at least theoretically, and so a person is not free to choose even if they feel they are.
c.Genetic: since our genes
already determine, to some extent at least, our character, we cannot be fully
responsible for some of our actions, as we are not for the inherited diseases
we develop.
For instance, amongst certain, usually rather conservative groups there has
been a change in the attitude to homosexuality: if it was a (partly) genetic
trait, as some recent evidence has suggested, then it should no longer be
considered a sin (-- even though homosexual behaviour might still be.)
d.Social: the way someone has been brought up and their experiences determine, to some extent at least, how they will behave -- e.g. more often violently if they come from the inner city, and more often studiously if they come from a certain kind of middle class family, so it cannot all be their fault, or to their credit.
Exercise 3.3.:
''Fatalism [is the] doctrine that all events occur
according to a fixed and inevitable destiny that is neither controlled nor
affected by the individual will. Fatalism is frequently confused with
determinism, the doctrine that events are determined by the events that precede
them. According to fatalism, however, preceding events have no causal
connection with the events that follow. A fated event takes place not according
to a natural law but in accordance with some mysterious decree issued by some
mysterious power, perhaps ages before. Determinism, in its tenet that every
event has its determining conditions in its immediate antecedents, which may
include the human will, is consistent with a belief in the efficacy of the
human will, but fatalism is not.
Both fatalism and determinism, thus distinguished
from each other, should likewise be distinguished from predestination.
Predestination is determination plus the belief in a supernatural power that
has established a determining natural sequence of causes. Fatalism is a belief
in a supernatural power that predetermines without recourse to natural order.
Fatalism appeared among the ancient Hebrews,
Greeks, and Romans and is particularly prevalent today among Muslims. In the
modern West, though, it has retained a degree of acceptance only where science
has not had a controlling influence in developing the doctrine of causality''
(Microsoft, Encarta, 1996.)
It may be that if I don't know -- and cannot ever know -- what is predetermined, or predestined, then I am still 'sufficiently' capable of free action to be held responsible. (Another, more rigorous answer is suggested below.)
Picture of Kant from: Microsoft Encarta
96.
Picture of Nietzsche from: Microsoft Bookshelf 1993.